Tamar Ziegler and I’ve simply uploaded to the arXiv our paper “Infinite partial sumsets within the primes“. This can be a brief paper impressed by a current results of Kra, Moreira, Richter, and Robertson (mentioned for example in this Quanta article from final December) displaying that for any set of pure numbers of constructive higher density, there exists a sequence
of pure numbers and a shift
such that
for all
this solutions a query of ErdÅ‘s). In view of the “transference precept“, it’s then believable to ask whether or not the identical end result holds if
is changed by the primes. We are able to present the next outcomes:
Theorem 1
We comment that it was proven by Balog that there (unconditionally) exist arbitrarily lengthy however finite sequences of primes such that
is prime for all
. (This end result may also be recovered from the later outcomes of Ben Inexperienced, myself, and Tamar Ziegler.) Additionally, it had beforehand been proven by Granville that on the Hardy-Littlewood prime tuples conjecture, there existed growing sequences
and
of pure numbers such that
is prime for all
.
The conclusion of (i) is stronger than that of (ii) (which is after all in keeping with the previous being conditional and the latter unconditional). The conclusion (ii) additionally implies the well-known theorem of Maynard that for any given , there exist infinitely many
-tuples of primes of bounded diameter, and certainly our proof of (ii) makes use of the identical “Maynard sieve” that powers the proof of that theorem (although we use a formulation of that sieve nearer to that in this weblog put up of mine). Certainly, the failure of (iii) principally arises from the failure of Maynard’s theorem for dense subsets of primes, just by eradicating these clusters of primes which might be unusually intently spaced.
Our proof of (i) was initially impressed by the topological dynamics strategies utilized by Kra, Moreira, Richter, and Robertson, however we managed to condense it to a purely elementary argument (taking over solely half a web page) that makes no reference to topological dynamics and builds up the sequence recursively by repeated software of the prime tuples conjecture.
The proof of (ii) takes up the vast majority of the paper. It’s best to phrase the argument when it comes to “prime-producing tuples” – tuples for which there are infinitely many
with
all prime. Maynard’s theorem is equal to the existence of arbitrarily lengthy prime-producing tuples; our theorem is equal to the stronger assertion that there exist an infinite sequence
such that each preliminary phase
is prime-producing. The primary new instrument for attaining that is the next cute measure-theoretic lemma of Bergelson:
Lemma 2 (Bergelson intersectivity lemma) Let
be subsets of a chance area
of measure uniformly bounded away from zero, thus
. Then there exists a subsequence
such that
for all
.
This lemma has a brief proof, although not a wholly apparent one. Firstly, by deleting a null set from , one can assume that each one finite intersections
are both constructive measure or empty. Secondly, a routine software of Fatou’s lemma reveals that the maximal perform
has a constructive integral, therefore should be constructive in some unspecified time in the future
. Thus there’s a subsequence
whose finite intersections all comprise
, thus have constructive measure as desired by the earlier discount.
It seems that one can’t fairly mix the usual Maynard sieve with the intersectivity lemma as a result of the occasions that present up (which roughly correspond to the occasion that
is prime for some random quantity
(with a well-chosen chance distribution) and a few shift
) have their chance going to zero, fairly than being uniformly bounded from beneath. To get round this, we borrow an thought from a paper of Banks, Freiberg, and Maynard, and group the shifts
into varied clusters
, chosen in such a means that the chance that no less than one of
is prime is bounded uniformly from beneath. One then applies the Bergelson intersectivity lemma to these occasions and makes use of many purposes of the pigeonhole precept to conclude.